Photographing some other possible worlds
This page gives overviews of some of my papers. You can use the links below to jump to the corresponding point on the page.
Injustice in the Spaces Between Concepts
Transformative Learning in the Prison Classroom
Epistemic Injustice through Transformative Learning
Teachers’ Existential Self-Doubt as a Form of Epistemic Self-Doubt,
Mental Illness and the Naturalism Debate
The Ethical Dimension of Lethal Specimen Collection in Ornithology
Advanced Modals, Advanced Quantifiers, and Reduction
The Extensional Adequacy of Lewis’ Counterfactual Analysis
Prison Teaching and the Aims of Education
Injustice in the Spaces Between Concepts
Published in the Southern Journal of Philosophy, (2020), Volume 58, Issue 1.
DOI: 10.1111/sjp.12349
I argue that epistemic injustice manifests not only in the content of our concepts, but in the spaces between them. Others have shown that epistemic injustice arises in the form of ‘testimonial injustice’ - where an agent is harmed because her credibility is undervalued - and ‘hermeneutical injustice’ - where an agent is harmed because some community lacks the conceptual resources that would allow her to render her experience intelligible. I think that epistemic injustice also arises as a result of prejudiced and harmful defects in the inferential architecture of both scientific practice and everyday thinking. Drawing on lessons from the philosophy of science, I argue that the inferential architecture of our epistemic practices can be prejudiced and wrongful, leading to a variety of epistemic injustice that I am calling ‘inferential injustice.’ This type of injustice is fully structural; it inheres in our epistemic practices themselves rather than as a direct result of an individual’s action. For this reason, cases of inferential injustice are importantly different from extant cases of epistemic injustice and are especially hard to track. We need a better understanding of inferential injustice so that we can avoid and ameliorate cases such as the ones I present here.
Trust, Power, and Transformation in the Prison Classroom
Published in the Journal of Prison & Education and Reentry, (2021), Volume 7, Number 2.
DIO: https://doi.org/10.25771/0694-3a92
This article does three things. First, it asks a new question about transformative education that has heretofore not been sufficiently investigated, namely ‘what is the role of power and trust in the decision of whether to transform one’s meaning scheme in the face of new information or whether to simply reject the new information?’ Secondly, it develops a five-stage model of transformative learning which gives an account of what determines the way a student will react to disorienting dilemmas. Finally, uses grounded-theory along with the proposed five-stage model to argue that power and trust play an important role in establishing transformative learning experiences. Specifically, I interviewed 19 educators who teach in correctional facilities about their experiences. The data collected indicates that trust and power are particularly important at stages 3 and 4 of my suggested five-stage model where the student is at a crossroads as to whether to revise their existing meaning schemes or merely to reject the new information.
Epistemic Injustice through Transformative Learning
Forthcoming in the Journal of Philosophy of Education.
In this paper, I argue that epistemic injustice can result from transformative learning. Transformative learning causes a radical change in the structure of a student’s personal epistemic resources to bring them in line with the structure of a discipline’s shared epistemic resources. When those shared epistemic resources are biased, this transformation prevents students from retaining aspects of their personal epistemic resources which it is strongly in their interests (as well as in the interests of the broader epistemic community) to retain. In these cases, transformative learning causes epistemic injustice in the form of inferential injustice.
Teachers’ Existential Self-Doubt as a Form of Epistemic Self-Doubt
Published in Philosophy of Education Quarterly, (2022), 78(1): 34-37.
Mordechai Gordon’s essay considers two central notions — epistemic self-doubt and existential self-doubt — and identifies an instance of the latter which occurs specifically for educators. I will use Gordon’s framing to draw out interesting relationships between epistemic and existential self-doubt that help further analyze the interesting teacher-case that Gordon brings attention to. I’ll begin by offering further analysis of the two central cases of epistemic self-doubt offered by Gordon and offering some further, distinct cases. I will then present some ways in which epistemic and existential self-doubt might be importantly related. Finally, I will suggest that the cases I have offered can help illuminate a way of further understanding Gordon’s teacher-case, which makes it an essentially epistemic kind of existential self-doubt. I hope that this further analysis will help develop Gordon’s analysis by exposing some ways in which existential self-doubt experienced by teachers qua teachers can be distinctive.
Mental Illness and the Naturalism Debate
This paper introduces and explains a particular interesting phenomenon.
Interesting Phenomenon: very able and informed theorists sometimes act as though they agree with claims which, in the cold light of day, they would certainly reject.
It introduces the interesting phenomenon by presenting an exemplifying case; the mental illness literature. It explains it by introducing a new notion; the notion of an ‘inference web’.
I argue here that the mental illness literature operates against a backdrop of bad inferences. By this I mean that there are common inferences and associations made in the literature at large that i) are bad, ii) would be rejected by participants in the literature if brought into the cold light of day, iii) are almost invisible even to those who make them. To explain this, I bring in the notion of an inference web; a web-like structure of inferences that underly a discipline or research project and form a shared backdrop against which discourse can happen. As a toy example, if I state that P is true, and you set out to refute my claim by showing the P is impossible, you take my claim that P is true to license the claim that P is possible. This is quite right. We all know that things that are true are also possibly true, and hence your response to me is justified. This is an inference (or association) that forms part of the web of inferences (or associations) that are permitted by our discipline. They are moves that we all are allowed to make without (except in exceptional circumstances, for example when defending a certain position in modal metaphysics) excess justification and without even bringing that move to light.
Moves like this one are knitted into the fabric of our discourse. But they can go wrong. When they do go wrong, they are especially pernicious because their very nature makes them hard to catch and because their centrality or ‘fixedness’ in our discourses makes them hard to avoid.
The paper proceeds as follows: in §1, I gloss the mental illness literature. In §2, I introduce the interesting phenomenon. In §3, I introduce the notion of an inference web. And in §4, I show how inference webs can explain the interesting phenomenon.
The Ethical Dimension of Lethal Specimen Collection in Ornithology
Co-authored with Vanya Rohwer
Ornithologists and researchers routinely kill and collect bird specimens for research, education, and conservation. Many object to this practice on ethical grounds, arguing that this endangers the very species that researchers claim to care about, or that the taking of a life in the name of research is never justified. The researchers in question then respond by citing data on populations to prove their work in no way endangers species or arguing that conservation and (hence) ethical considerations should be made at the species (rather than individual) level.
We investigate this literature, especially as it pertains to ornithology. Rather than assessing individual arguments, we identify problematic inferences made in the literature as a whole using the notion of inference webs to explain the prevalence of these mistakes. An inference web is a structured collection of claims and inferences that frames our reasoning in a given area.We argue that there is a problematic inference web in the background of this literature resulting in assumptions that i) are bad and ii) would be rejected by the people who make them if asked directly.
For example, many arguments in favor of collection assume that cost-benefit analyses are the most poignant way to assess research. This is so even though in another context researchers would deny the relevant considerations are reducible to mere costs and benefits. Firstly, almost all of them undoubtedly think the benefits derived from collecting go far beyond preserving biological diversity. It’s clear that conservation efforts, for which collection is necessary, aim at a huge variety of ends over-and-above protection of individual species. Sometimes the aim is to preserve information for further scientific study of ecological and evolutionary forces. Sometimes it’s to preserve features of nature important for human enjoyment. In these instances, arguing that collection is ethical on the basis of cost-benefit analyses misses the most important concerns in favor of collection. Second, most researchers would acknowledge the growing literature about deep and prevailing problems with the concept of ‘species’ as well as the extensive literature suggesting biodiversity is not best measured by counting the number of species conserved.
Our aim here is not simply to reject arguments but to improve on them. According to our account, the problematic inference webs that pervade this literature foreclose discussion of more productive views. Once we clear the ground of these problematic arguments, we can set the stage for more productive debates.
Advanced Modals, Advanced Quantifiers, and Reduction
I offer a solution to the problem of advanced modalizing which is supposed to show that genuine modal realism is unable to accommodate claims like ‘possibly, there are many possible worlds.’ I argue that, given the ontology of modal realism, those claims are simply not apt to be modalized.
The Extensional Adequacy of Lewis’ Counterfactual Analysis
In ‘Counterfactuals and Explanation’ (2006) Boris Kment argues that David Lewis’ (1973, 1979, 1986) counterfactual analysis is extensionally inadequate by offering what he thinks is a counterexample to Lewis’ criteria for assessing the similarity of possible worlds. I defend Lewis against Kment by showing that Kment’s case is not a counterexample to Lewis’ theory. Lewis requires that regions of exact match are continuous and spatially maximal, but Kment’s counterexample assumes that discontinuous, non-spatially maximal regions can also contribute to exact match. If we assess exact match properly and as Lewis intended, Lewis’ analysis is safe.
Prison Teaching and the Aims of Education
Arguments for college education in prison (hereafter ‘prison education’) usually cite its effect on recidivism rates, claiming that we ought to support prison education because it helps us achieve our rehabilitative goals and - mostly due to this effect – saves taxpayers money. This kind of approach focuses on prison education as aiding in the goals of incarceration. I argue that prison education is also in line with the aims of higher education (hereafter ‘education’) and that is why we should support it. More specifically, prison education helps us to achieve one of the main epistemic aims of education and hence, as educators, we should support it.